They must not believe in God
“They must not believe in God.”
These words from my daughter came after a
conversation we had been having at bedtime about someone who she had
heard yelling at their baby. For her, it was clear: someone who
believed in God simply would not do something as monstrous as scream
“shut up!” at an infant. People who believe in God don’t do such
things, after all. Right?
Needless to say, an interesting
conversation followed. We talked about how all kinds of people who
believe all kinds of things exhibit all kinds of behaviours. We talked
about belief and behaviour and the connection between the two. We
talked about how we don’t always do the good we ought (or want) to do
and how we sometimes do the bad we don’t want to do (Romans 7:14-25). We talked about repentance and forgiveness and redemption. It was an eventful bedtime—at least, more eventful than usual.
And, of course, is set my mind a-whirring
on timeless question of the grounds of goodness. Is God required to
legitimate objective goodness? Can we be good without God? What about
the bad behaviour of those who claim to know God? These are old, old
questions dating at least as far back as Plato’s Euthyphro and
have constituted the subject matter of countless books and articles and
lectures and conversations in coffee shops ever since.
They are also the subject of a recent post called “Good Minus God” by University of Massachusetts Amherst philosopher Louise Antony, for The Stone, the New York Times’ philosophy
blog. I didn’t have high expectations in clicking the link, truth be
told. This way of framing the issue is rarely helpful, and it seems
always to centre on either, a) demonstrating that there exist good
people who do not believe in God (hardly a revelation); or b) that
belief in God is required to do good (at least the right kind) in the
world, depending on whether it is atheism or theism being advocated.
Regrettably, my low expectations were barely met.
Antony offers a fairly predictable
critique of “divine command theory” (D.C.T.) and “divine independence
theory” (D.I.T.). In the former case, if things are only good because
God decrees that they be so, then anything God decrees is good and
goodness is arbitrary. The illustrative example is equally predictable:
“If God were to command you to eat your children, then it would be
‘right’ to eat your children.” In the latter case, if what is good is independent of God—that is, if God prefers it because is good—then its goodness obtains its existence and resides outside of God, therefore God is unnecessary.
But
surely there are better ways of framing the connection between goodness
and God. What about, for example, the possibility that God is
inherently good and loving? What if there is no contradiction between a
property owing its existence to God and it being constitutive
of God’s identity? What about the possibility that in creating us in his
image, God made us to resonate with and respond to what is good? What
if our human evaluating and deliberating upon matters of good/bad,
right/wrong is not us defining or determining what is good, but responding, more or less accurately, to the goodness that precedes, surrounds, guides, and leads us?
For me, this provides a better image of
both God and human beings. God does not arbitrarily decide that some
things are good and some are bad just to see if his puppets will dance
accordingly, and we do not slavishly obey and align ourselves with a
dictatorial God’s commands simply because “God said so.” Part of what
it means to bear God’s image, it seems to me, is to share a deep and
intrinsic connection to goodness. As believers, we do not (or ought
not) behave ourselves out of fear or duty or out of the promise of
reward or punishment, as Antony suggests in this post. Rather we strive
to do what is good out of a God-given hunger and longing, however
fitfully and incoherently this is understood or expressed, to be and to
do what we were made to be and to do.
Of course commands are necessary at various points in the human story. Of course we do not and cannot comprehensively apprehend the scope of what is good and true and beautiful. Of course
we do not always live consistently with what we do know of these
things. This is part of what it means to be fallen creatures, whether
we believe in God or not. We are complicated beings who believe and do
things for a dizzying amount and variety of reasons, some good, some
bad.
As disappointing as I found Antony’s
construal of the view that God is necessary for good, I was even more
surprised by how little she had to say about the atheistic justification
for goodness. This is about all we are offered:
We “moralistic atheists” do not see right
and wrong as artifacts of a divine protection racket. Rather, we find
moral value to be immanent in the natural world, arising from the
vulnerabilities of sentient beings and from the capacities of rational
beings to recognize and to respond to those vulnerabilities and
capacities in others.
Aside from the fact that there is nothing inconsistent between believing that the above tells part of the story and believing
that God is involved in the process, this simply isn’t very much to go
on. Why might such a thing as morality be immanent in the natural
world? Why might our species alone among sentient beings have the
capacity to identify and reflect upon and respond to this immanent
property? Why, for that matter, might sentience and consciousness be
linked to morality? At some level, the answer will undoubtedly be
linked to some kind of evolutionary advantage that these
capacities conferred upon their possessors, but these questions are
mostly left untouched.
At any rate, after reading this post my
thoughts returned to my conversation with my daughter. How would I like
for her to understand the connection between God and goodness? How
would I like her to understand our human inconsistencies and confusions
when it comes to what we believe and what we do? How would I like for
her to understand and affirm the goodness that she sees around her,
whatever its professed source?
Quite simply, I think, I would like for
her to know that God is good, that he has made (all of) us to long for,
respond to, and participate in goodness, and that all people—whatever
they “believe” about God—resist God and resist good. Most of all, I
think that I would like her to know that God delights in, longs for, and
pursues his children with a fierce and determined goodness. The good,
the bad, the ugly, the beautiful, the confused and conflicted, the
rebellious, the joyful, the just-about-convinced, the hard-hearted and
stubborn, the fearful, the expectant and hopeful.
Which is to say, all of us.
Originally posted at Rumblings